Uno dei drammi del
nostro tempo è la decadenza dell’arte – intesa a “tuttotondo”, cioè sia visiva
sia musicale sia architettonica – se non addirittura il suo annientamento e la sua
sostituzione con il nulla, il vuoto, una parete bianca, un suono stridulo
indecifrabile, ecc., in poche parole con la non-arte. Un tempo si coltivava l’arte del bello; oggi
si coltiva e ci si appaga del brutto, tributandogli una sorta di culto, ... molto
politicamente ed ecclesiasticamente corretto.
Anche la Chiesa, un tempo grande mecenate, cultrice delle arti e negli ultimi secoli ultimo
baluardo contro l’avanzare della bruttezza, sembra essersi del tutto assuefatta
a questa mentalità mondana del brutto e del vuoto, adeguando sia le chiese (ora, riduttivamente e quasi spregiativamente, definite semplicemente “aule liturgiche”,
sic!) sia la musica, compresa quella corale, a quel culto della
bruttezza … in nome di un’idea molto politicamente corretta …. di minimalismo,
di pauperismo, il quale altro non sarebbe che il volto ipocrita della sobrietà.
Sul tema, a Dio
piacendo, in futuro, avremo modo di dire qualcosa, dimostrando come esso sia
falso e sia contrario alla Divina Rivelazione ed alla stessa Tradizione della
Chiesa.
Nel frattempo, ci
piace dar rilievo ad un interesse contributo – in inglese – su ciò che ha
rimpiazzato l’arte negli ultimi decenni.
Harold Boatrite : “Art and Its Replacements”
FR.
ROBERT C. PASLEY, KCHS
I would like to introduce the readers of NLM to an American composer, a native Philadelphian, and a great friend of sacred music, Harold Boatrite. Dr. Boatrite’s article, “Art and its Replacements,” appeared in the most recent issue of “Sacred Music.”
Harold Boatrite was born on April
2, 1932, in Philadelphia, Pennsylvania. After early studies with Stanley
Hollingsworth, he was awarded a fellowship to the Tanglewood Music Center where
he studied composition with Lukas Foss and took part in the orchestration
seminars of Aaron Copland. In 1961 he was invited by Rudolf Serkin to be
composer-in-residence at the Marlboro Music Festival.
He received an honorary doctorate
in 1967 from the Combs College of Music and subsequently was appointed to the
faculty of Haverford College, where he taught theory and composition until
1980. During that time (1974 to 1977) he served on the music panel of the
Pennsylvania Council on the Arts.
In honor of his fiftieth birthday
in 1982, a series of concerts devoted exclusively to his music was presented by
the Pennsylvania Alliance for American Music. Among the participants in the
series were the Chamber Orchestra of Philadelphia, the Thomas Jefferson
University Choir and the Mendelssohn Club of Philadelphia. Boatrite has written
in a wide variety of media ranging from solo and chamber pieces to large-scale
choral and orchestral works. His music has been heard throughout the United
States and in Europe, most notably, at the Prague Autumn International Music
Festival.
He has received many commissions
including a concerto for piano and orchestra for the National Association of
Composers USA, a concerto for harpsichord and strings commissioned by Temple
Painter, Fantasia on a Gregorian Tune for string orchestra, harpsichord, celesta
and boy choir commissioned by the Samuel S. Fels Fund, and a ballet, “Childermas,”
for CBS-TV which premiered on national television in 1969.
In 1992 Boatrite was appointed
composer-in-residence for the Conductors Institute at the University of South
Carolina. He served for many years as new music consultant to the Chamber
Orchestra of Philadelphia. His chamber music is recorded on the Capstone label
and his orchestral scores are housed in the Edwin A. Fleisher Orchestral
Collection, Free Library of Philadelphia.
Dr. Boatrite has written various
sacred pieces. His “Ave Maria” has been used many times at Mater Ecclesiae,
Berlin, NJ. His work “Benedicta Filia,” was premiered at the 2009 Mater
Ecclesiae Assumption Mass. He has dealt with the philosophical battle
concerning beauty and form in music for many years. In this battle as a
composer, he has had to resist and fight against many bizarre musical theories.
I gladly post his thought provoking reflection.
Art and Its Replacements
Art is a slippery word that lends itself readily to equivocation and confusion because of its many possible meanings: the art of medicine, terms of art as found in law, the liberal arts, art as workmanship, and so on. We are concerned here with the particular kind of equivocation that occurs when the word is applied to painting, sculpture, architecture, music, and poetry.
While any number of critics and scholars have engaged in obfuscations of varying complexity, Morse Peckham has said simply that “ ... the term art at this point appears to be an empty category. ...”[1] This is a statement intriguing not only for its apparent simplicity but also for its striking resemblance to a conjuring trick. ““Art [now you see it] ... appears to be [this is the abracadabra] ... an empty category” [poof! art vanishes].
Like actual conjuring tricks,
this statement seems to present us with a paradox: How can something be
simultaneously nothing? Moreover, the statement offers us limitless
possibilities for creative expression. If art is an empty category, the artist
is free to explore and exploit the uncharted land of whatever and to fill the
empty category with anything at all. Thus the illusion expands until, of
course, we begin to examine it logically.
Categories are filled solely with
the meanings of the terms by which they are named. The category horse, for
example is filled with the denotation and connotations of the word “horse.” Thus,
if “art” is an empty category, “art” is an empty or
meaningless term. But if “art” is a meaningless term, then the statement “art
is an empty category” is equally meaningless, and what we thought was a
wondrous paradox turns out to be just another self-contradictory proposition.
(Logically speaking, the only empty category is the categorynothing.)
But we still have not discovered
how the conjuring trick is done. Let us look more closely at the “empty
category.” Lo, we find that it is not entirely empty. Glimmering subtly in the
background are the connotations of the word “art”; it is only
the denotative meaning that has disappeared, and its disappearance creates the
illusion of an empty category.
Sleight of word is found also in
modern political propaganda, which frequently removes denotative meanings with
their limitations and responsibilities in order to capitalize irresponsibly on
the connotations with their limitless possibilities--for example, National
Socialism, in which the denotative meaning of “socialism” is removed
in order to promote fascism, the very opposite of socialism; or People’s
Republic, in which the denotative meaning of “republic” is removed in
order to promote dictatorship. The retention of the connotative meanings in
both these examples is the key to their success as propaganda. The illusion
that the words somehow mean what they meant before is successfully effected
because the connotations remain, even though the substantive meanings have been
changed.
Now it is obvious from its
selective use historically that “art” is a term so rich in meaning and with
such cachet that almost anybody would like, so to speak, to
get his hands on it, and “anybody” is an extraordinarily large number of
people, so there are thousands upon thousands currently claiming the category art for
their products, regardless of how distantly, if at all, related to art these
products may be. Such claims are made possible by the same sleight of word
found in Peckham’s “empty category” and in the examples of political propaganda
cited above.
The Oxford English
Dictionary defines “art” as “the skillful production of the beautiful
in visible forms.” This is its denotative meaning. Among its myriad
connotations are importance, creativity, significance, mystery, transcendence.
Removing the denotation makes it possible to call anything art, ascribing to it
all the connotations of the term. The magical word is pronounced, and
--presto!-- a gouge in the wall, several minutes of silence, drop cloths, fecal
matter--all become works of art.
But this transformation is not
without its difficulties. Convincing people that a gouge in the wall is
sculpture or that several minutes of silence are music takes considerable political skill,
for these things must be presented in an art environment in collusion with
officials of an art establishment. The gouge must be in the wall of an art
museum; the several minutes of silence in a concert hall with a musical
instrument and a would-be performer standing by. Elaborate explanations in the
form of catalogues or program notes play a necessary role in persuasion and
mystification. Indeed, the very existence of these products as art depends on
advertising and presentation. But no matter how clever the propaganda--and
despite the mountain of books, catalogues, program notes, and critical
reviews--the two perennial questions continue to be asked by the general and
the not-so-general public: Is it art? and, What is it?
These questions are usually
parried with the assertion that the public is ignorant and uneducated in these
matters. This idea is then put forth as the reason for the issuance of all the
above-described verbiage, i.e., the public needs to be informed and enlightened
about the new “art.” Nevertheless, since these questions perdure, one suspects
that the answers already exist in the minds of the questioners. “Is it art”?
The unstated answer is, “No.” “What is it?” The unstated answer: “Whatever it
happens to be.” A gouge in the wall is just that and nothing more, even when it
is in a museum wall. Silence, albeit in a concert hall, is certainly not music.
In the past, defacing a museum
wall or mounting canned feces on a pedestal in an exhibition would have caused
scandal or outrage--or perhaps, among the more cynically minded, amusement; but
lately, the ability of these things to shock has diminished to such a point
that they evoke scarcely a shrug. The attitude of the public now ranges from
mild annoyance and boredom to indifference, and so our would-be artists have
resorted to religious desecration in order to regain active public attention. And
regain it they have, but perhaps not quite in the way they intended. People are
not reacting to the alleged works of art as art but rather to the blasphemy or
sacrilege they engender. Thus, any effective existence as art that the works
might have had is cancelled. But the gouge in the wall and the drop cloth have
no such distractions: they simply replace art.
Therefore a new category must be
invented to describe more accurately these phenomena and perhaps to define more
clearly their purposes. Since they are not art but insistently claim to be art,
let us call them non-art. The silence, the feces, the hole in the
wall are obvious examples chosen for the sake of clarity, but they are not
extreme cases when compared to the non-artist who had himself crucified atop an
automobile, or the fellow who “sculpted” himself nearly to death as he recorded
his progress on film.
Non-art ranges widely, from the
very obvious examples just mentioned to more subtle œuvres like
so-called action painting, certain kinds of atonal “music,” and various
post-modernist fabrications. The more subtle types employ traditional art
materials such as paint and the framed canvas or conventional musical
instruments. The use of traditional art materials makes it somewhat more
difficult to discern these types for what they are. Non-art objects often bear
little resemblance to each other, and it is therefore necessary to introduce
several sub-categories in order to provide a framework for critical
analysis.
Hegel, in his theory of
dialectic, posits that every idea gives rise to or contains its opposite. Let
us enlarge somewhat upon this by adding that every idea can give rise also to
its imitation and its substitution. Many examples of all three of these processes
can be found in the natural world as well as in human endeavors: the opposition of
predator and prey, the imitation of poisonous by non-poisonous
snakes, the substitution by birds of their eggs in the nests
of other species, and so forth. The presence of these processes in human
activity is so pervasive and obvious that we need cite only examples in the
field of art.
In deference to Hegel, then, we
shall begin with opposition. This process produces a sub-category that we shall
call anti-art. All those works that purposely cause an
experience of ugliness are in this sub-category. In the case of discursive or
representational work, we must distinguish the work itself from its message,
e.g., a mediæval painting of the Crucifixion of Christ, in which the event
portrayed is horrendously ugly, but the painting is sublimely beautiful. In
contrast, a concerto for circular saw and orchestra, an exhibit featuring
electrified barbed wire with cautionary signs, and a string quartet emitting
twenty minutes of systematic and relentless cacophony all aim successfully at
being as ugly as possible, explanations to the contrary notwithstanding. We
should also place in this sub-category the canned feces, the religious
desecration, the self-sculpture, and the automobile crucifixion that was not
portrayed but actually happened. These examples of anti-art differ
sharply in character. The string quartet uses traditional art materials as
described earlier and could easily be mistaken for art, whereas canned human
waste is merely disgusting.
The second process, imitation,
gives rise to the sub-category we shall call quasi-art. As its name
suggests, quasi-art is like art but differs essentially from it in that
quasi-art retains only the features of this or that style and lacks the
substantive character of genuine art. It is often difficult to define precisely
what the substantive element is in many works of authentic art, although its
absence in quasi-art is almost immediately evident. Gesture without substance
distinguishes quasi-art, commonly known as kitsch.
“Decorator” paintings that stand
in for authentic art fill many commercial galleries. Impressionist and
post-impressionist styles lend themselves especially well to this form of
quasi-art. The mass-produced Paris street scenes as well as landscapes with the
inevitable flying birds in the background have been consistently remunerative.
The endless procession of porcelain dolls and of illustrated plates has also
proved lucrative. Much cinematic background music makes eclectic use of
gestures from various historical periods without the essential ingredients of
real melody and over-all form. The post-modernist collage of styles without
synthesis is exactly the same thing, but because it is presented as independent
music, it is seen, curiously, as a new development, even though it has existed
in films for over eighty years. Post-modernist architecture that takes as its
defining ideal the Las Vegas Strip must be regarded as kitsch par
excellence.
Perhaps the most significant use
of quasi-art in the twentieth century has been its role in political
propaganda, specifically in the architecture, the painting, and the sculpture
of the fascist states and the “socialist realism” of the Marxist regimes.
Because quasi-art uses gestures from earlier periods, it has a familiarity that
makes it appealing to large numbers of people. Since there is nothing in it to
challenge the intellect and thereby to distract from the political message, it
has been a powerfully effective medium for the dissemination of some of modern
history’s most irrational notions.
The process of substitution we
shall categorize as pseudo-art, and it is nothing more than
the replacing of art with relatively inoffensive things that would, under any
other circumstances, never be recognized as art: the wrapping of public
buildings, functionless walls and fences, blank canvases and empty frames,
planks, slabs, a pile of broken glass, and again the silence in place of music.
While anti-art is at least ugly, and quasi-art is at best pretty or cute, the
principal characteristic of pseudo-art seems to be its sheer inanity--nothing
presented as something, nonsense enthroned as art.
These sub-categories of non-art
are in theory separate and distinct, and for this article the clearest and
simplest examples have been chosen as illustrations: but in many “works” of
non-art, the particular sub-category may not be obvious. Thus it is for the
reader to apply to each case the principles outlined here and to decide for
himself whether the work perceived is non-art, and, if it is, what sub-category
it falls into, and also whether it has characteristics of another sub-category.
For instance, a pile of broken glass might be displayed in such a way as to
appear dangerous. The natural reaction would be to distance oneself or to be
repelled. Hence, the pile of broken glass would have characteristics of both
pseudo-art and anti-art. A wallpaper pattern framed and presented as art would
have elements of both quasi-art and pseudo-art.
Non-art is a direct result of the
modernist obsession with novelty. Endless experimentation in the frantic quest
for originality has inevitably led to something essentially different from art.
Once we understand that not everything presented as art really is art, it
should be a relatively simple task to determine which sub-categories non-art
concoctions fall into.
But none of these categories can
have any real meaning without a clear understanding of what authentic or
genuine art is. So we will start with a simple definition: art is the human
creation of things of beauty. Of course, this raises the question of what is
meant by the term beauty. The simple answer: beauty is an order indicating
perfection. Basic examples of such an order would include the geometric circle
in the visual arts; in music, the pattern of intervals in a fundamental chord; [2] metrical forms in verse;
and, in architecture, the Roman arch in all its practical utility. While none
of these models is perfect in itself, all point to or indicate perfection
because they immediately approximate their exemplars. Mere circles approximate
perfect circles. Basic chords approximate perfect chords. But viewing a bare
circle or listening to a basic chord for any appreciable length of time would
doubtless result in boredom for the viewer or listener (modern minimalism
notwithstanding). Even though each of these examples is an order indicating
perfection, all are but simple elements of what would be a larger or complex
order indicating perfection. The idea of creating such an order
necessitates a consideration of creativity.
The modernist consensus is that
creativity is originality. If this notion were true, it would have universal
application, i.e., it would be true for all periods and styles everywhere. But
a brief glance at history reveals a very different story. Painters deliberately
copied from other painters. Composers built on the material of other composers.
The same holds true for poets and architects. Through tradition, entire styles
evolved from earlier styles. Originality in works of art was unheard of. Yet
within any given style there were differences among the artists. As composers,
J. S. Bach and Domenico Scarlatti were Baroque in style, but in content, they
were very different from each other. The contrast between Victorian poets
Robert Browning and Alfred, Lord Tennyson, is striking, although both used
meter, rhyme, verse and the English language. Notre Dame cathedral in Paris and
the cathedral at Cologne are two vastly different worlds, but both are Gothic
in style. Artists worked within the parameters of a tradition because they knew
that at least part of their purpose was communication and that without
tradition there could be no language. Because each artist was a unique person,
his creative work expressed his individuality as opposed to the endless
fabrication of novelties for their own sake.
Thus it is coherent self
expression that defines creativity and not the pursuit of originality,
which leads only to the dead end of non-art. This is by no means a condemnation
of those artists in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries who have, despite
the pressure of current trends, continued to add their unique contributions to
the tradition, developing it and at the same time preserving it. Theirs is an
often thankless task in a society devoutly committed to the latest fashions.
For these artists, in the words of composer Walter Piston: “Fashion is the enemy
of creativity.”
So the genuine artist expresses
himself coherently when he constructs a complex order indicating perfection
using the language appropriate to his medium. The ability to imagine such an
order and then to make it a physical reality is known as creative talent. The
word talent implies a certain exclusivity. Not everyone has it, and if the
above description of it is true and accurate, creative talent must indeed be a
rare phenomenon. This is, of course, in direct opposition to the egalitarian
notion that everybody has creative talent and therefore anybody can be an
artist: hence the innumerable composers, poets, painters, sculptors, etc.,
facilitated by the virtual disappearance of objective standards.
But all is not lost. It is
possible to recover those standards by a careful historical examination of all
the factors that commonly occur in great works of art and to draw conclusions
that would effectively function as criteria for the creation of new works as
well as for critical analysis and judgment. This is, in fact, what contemporary
artists who are involved in the creation of beautiful and communicative works
are actually doing, though they may not be conscious of it in the terms
described here. Perhaps the greatest difficulty for the creative artist is the
very act of imagining a complex order indicating perfection.
The notion of perfection itself is elusive and ambiguous. Thus an order
indicating it, is, to put it plainly, hard to find. Like the sub-atomic
particle, it could be here, and it might be there, but we know it exists
because, unlike the sub-atomic particle, it has been located with certainty, in
definite times and places, to wit: the aforementioned cathedrals, Michelangelo’s Pietà, the
paintings of Vermeer, Mozart’s Jupiter symphony, the poems of
Wordsworth, T. S. Eliot’s Four Quartets, and in a multitude of
other great works.
In the complex orders indicating
perfection, beauty is dynamic. It engages the
viewer or listener. Indicating perfection is an action involving
conflict and resolution. In music we hear it as dissonance resolving to
consonance. We see it in the play of symmetry and asymmetry in architecture and
the visual arts. In poetry, we see and hear it as enjambment in lines of verse
and in the irregular tumble of syllables over the meter. Within the most
turbulent works and in the very tranquil as well, the dialectic of conflict and
resolution is always present, however subtle or hidden it may be. The examples
given here are important but not exhaustive. We will not attempt to list the
many other ways in which it occurs. Suffice it to say that conflict and
resolution make beauty vibrant, and vibrant beauty is the essential
characteristic of all genuine art.
NOTES
[1] Morse Peckham, Man’s
Rage for Chaos [Chilton, 1965], p. 46.
[2] The first chord naturally
formed by the overtone series; the major triad.
Nessun commento:
Posta un commento